Traditional Chinese law v. Weberian legal rationality法理學英文論文_第1頁
Traditional Chinese law v. Weberian legal rationality法理學英文論文_第2頁
Traditional Chinese law v. Weberian legal rationality法理學英文論文_第3頁
Traditional Chinese law v. Weberian legal rationality法理學英文論文_第4頁
Traditional Chinese law v. Weberian legal rationality法理學英文論文_第5頁
已閱讀5頁,還剩13頁未讀, 繼續(xù)免費閱讀

下載本文檔

版權說明:本文檔由用戶提供并上傳,收益歸屬內(nèi)容提供方,若內(nèi)容存在侵權,請進行舉報或認領

文檔簡介

1、traditional chinese law v. weberian legal rationalityabstracta universal theory of law cannot be based on webers paradigm of the rationality of western law. abstraction and systematization of law are compared in western law and traditional chines codes. chinese law was not substantively irrational b

2、ut governed by ethical and status distinctions. chinese legislators worked with humanistic goals. the empiricism of traditional chinese law is as valid a form of intellectuality as the deductive rationality of civil law and the inductive rational-ity of common law.keywords: universal theory of law,

3、falv, formal and substantive irrationality, empirical law-finding, confucian ethics.1. universal theory of law and western particularitiessince jeremy bentham attempted his general jurisprudence, the efforts for a universal theory of law have been continuing for quite a while.1 the theory is indeed

4、significant especially in this global-ized world of cultural pluralism because such a theory, if completed, would solve the problem of a universal concept of law and construct one fundamental theory applicable to different legal systems in the world. only in this way could we really get rid of all t

5、he barriers to communication and mutual understanding between different legal systems and cultures. such a theory is not only necessary but even seems possible. among all the differences between different legal systems we find they share at least one commonality, which is what could be named as law

6、in english or falv in chinese and this makes the two terms generally inter-translatable. this basic commonality may be 1. jeremy bentham, of laws in general (london: athlone press, university of london, 1970).30 max weber studies max weber studies 2010.the basis for a possible universal theory of la

7、w. whatever the local peculiarities of different legal systems on the outside, this should not prevent us seeing the inner nature of law and constructing a universal theory of law. of all the local particularities, the western ones are likely to be the most dangerous and have caused the worst proble

8、ms. this is due to the dominant position that western law enjoys in the contemporary world and its overwhelming influence. chinas western-oriented legal reforms can be an example.2 chinese people, however, are not the only ones overwhelmed. very many western theorists of law are prepared to indulge

9、themselves in the current dominance of western law. but they may easily mistake their home particularities as being universal to all laws and cultures. this may well be one reason why the so-called general jurisprudence, which started in the west, has yet to be successful. for the sake of a sound ge

10、neral jurisprudence, the western forefathers need to step away from absolutizing western particularities.3 max weber constructed his theory of law, a part of which is his paradigm of legal rationality. with its supposed universality, this paradigm has been used by him and his followers to assess tra

11、di-tional chinese law and other non-western legal systems.4 typically, western laws, especially the continental tradition, are judged to be closest to the ideal type of rationality while traditional chinese and other non-western laws are placed on the irrational pole of the ideal type. but the quest

12、ion needs to be asked whether the weberian para-digm has successfully excluded its home particularities and accom-plished the goal of true universality. this paper seeks to investigate these questions through a re-examination of the weberian paradigm as applied to traditional chinese law. 2. zhang j

13、infan, the history of chinese law (beijing: china politics & law uni-versity press, 2002), p. 292. 3. su li, the rule of law and its local resources (beijing: china politics & law university press, 1996); william twining, globalisation & legal theory (london: but-terworths, 2000). 4. roberto unger,

14、following webers suit, first gave his own special definition of legality based on the european case, then claimed that true legality by his defini-tion can only be possible in western christian europe but never in the oriental or non-western world, so giving the european-based definition the additio

15、nal implica-tion of being universal. roberto unger, law in modern society: toward a criticism of social theory (new york: free press, 1976), p. 66. qian traditional chinese law v. weberian legal rationality 31 max weber studies 2010.2. distinctions between western rational naturalism and chinese emp

16、irical humanismwestern legal thought as a whole, with its rationalist traditionwhether anglo-american or continental, is today accepted as uniquely the best in human legal history, and this is even accepted in non-western countries like china. the confirmation of whether the western laws are really

17、so unique, or not, could be achieved by comparing the western legal system with that of pre-19th cen-tury china. contemporary scholars, both eastern and western, take these systems to be essentially different in nature.5 according to the weberian paradigm, one difference is that the traditional chin

18、ese law is not rational, both formally and substan-tively. the lack of formal rationality of traditional chinese law is usually observed by westerners from two technical perspectives: the lack of generalizability through abstraction and the lack of systematization.2.1. techniquesmax weber takes the

19、main characteristic of formally rational law as the supremacy of general abstract rules.6 it is argued that traditional chinese laws lacked formalistic discussions of abstract principles.7 of course the traditional chinese codes have also arrived at a certain degree of abstraction of social realitie

20、s. but the degree of abstrac-tion is much lower than that of the western codes. for example, the legal concept of social bonds in traditional chinese codes, appear in a more concrete way than their equivalents in the western laws. on the other hand, some general and abstract concepts, like legal per

21、son, or right, which have a high degree of abstraction and are fundamental to western laws, do not have their equivalents in tradi-tional chinese laws.8 5. fan zhongxin, coincidences and differences between chinese and western legal culture (beijing: china law & politics university press, 2001); gao

22、 daoyun, gao hongjun and he weifang (eds.), recent american academic writings on traditional chinese law (beijing: tsinghua university press, 2001). 6. max weber on law in economy and society,edited with an introduction by max rheinstein and translated by edward shils and max rheinstein (new york: s

23、imon & schuster, 1967), p. 354. 7. robert marsh, webers misunderstanding of traditional chinese law, american journal of sociology 106.2 (2000): 281-302. 8. yu jiang, formation and development of legal terminologies in contem-porary china, chinese and western legal traditions 01.1 (2001): 24-66.32 m

24、ax weber studies max weber studies 2010. with the lack of sufficient abstraction, from the point of view of european lawyers law then, the chinese system was remarkably rigid and limited in its capacity to deal with novel situations. it cor-rected for its rigidities and limitations with discretion,

25、judicial fiat, or ad hoc additions by the emperor.9 and this would often mean that the chinese judge did not have the formalized rules for the inter-pretation of statutesthe rules that would enable him to decide, as in western law, whether or not a particular statute covers the case before him.10 th

26、e second point is systemization. the structure of traditional chinese codes was simple aggregations of some empirical problem, with no internal logical systemization like that of western codes. this is also the result of the lack of reductive and abstract rationality. for example, the qing code stat

27、utes and sub-statutes were divided up according to their subject matters: fornication, repair of dikes, and so on. codes in other dynasties were similar.11 the way in which the codes were organized supports weber very well when he writes: the legally relevant fact situations were dis-tinguished from

28、 each other in a thoroughly empirical way in accor-dance with their objective characteristics rather than in accordance with their meanings as disclosed by formal legal logic.12 webers summary opinion of collections of laws and regulations like the chinese code (which he does not cite by title) was

29、that they have, in spite of a certain element of systematic classification, little to do with real codification; they are nothing but mechanical arrangements.13 in a word, why traditional china failed to develop categories of law that would produce separate bodies of law: a law of property, of contr

30、acts, of torts, of succession, and the like, as had happened in western law14 is because of the lack of formal rationality in lawmaking. therefore, although china has had a long and strong tradi-tion of codification, having a code is not the same as having legal 9. an example is the qing code, in wh

31、ich this rigidity caused the sub-statutes to be added to the code on ad hoc basis. 10. geoffrey maccormack, the spirit of traditional chinese law (athens: univer-sity of georgia press, 1996), p. 173. 11. wu shuchen, dictionary of traditional chinese legal culture (beijing: peking university press),

32、p. 100. 12. max weber on law, p. 80. 13. max weber on law, p. 271. 14. william c. jones, the great qing code (new york: oxford university press, 1994), pp. 16, 22. qian traditional chinese law v. weberian legal rationality 33 max weber studies 2010.rationality. nor does it eliminate discretion.15 ac

33、cording to ste-phen turner, all the institutions of traditional chinese law, were surrogates for an elaborated “l(fā)awyers law”not its equivalent.16 though the lack of abstraction in traditional chinese codes may remind people of webers comments on the empirical and induc-tive approach of anglo-america

34、n case law, essential differences exist between the two. in traditional china, deductive law-finding of the continental or roman kind, was not possible simply because the law was not organized into a hierarchy of categories.17 according to professor turner, the reason why empirical justice based on

35、analogy and precedentwhat are conventionally called inductive methods, like those of the common lawwas also not possible in china because of the key role of binding precedents.the key term is binding precedents, but it must be understood in a very specific contextthe problem of the creation of law b

36、y lawyers and judges to solve the various puzzles that the problem of law-finding throws up. one approach to law-finding, which we might call the justice approach, would be one in which the law that is chosen by the judge to be applied is simply the one which produces the most justice or best serves

37、 the interests of the community. one could also imagine this being done without binding precedent. in each new case, the judge would consult the law books and pick the law that produced justice, according to his lights or those of the community but his choice would not bind other judges in the futur

38、e to judge similarly. this is not how the empirical approach of the common law worked, and there was a crucial consequence of this difference which was utterly central to webers understanding of comparative law.18the common law can do this because it is also rationalized and its distinctiveness from

39、 the continental are in practice matters of degree, while its distinctiveness from traditional chinese law are matters of substance, due to the over-empirical nature and the insuf-ficiency of rationality in the intellectuality involved in traditional chinese lawmaking.19 thus, in terms of the techni

40、ques of law-finding, traditional chinese lawmaking employed much empirical intellectuality, which is not 15. s. turner, weber, the chinese legal system, and marshs critique, com-parative & historical sociology, 14.2 (2002): 6. /sectionchs/newsletter/chs02spr.pdf. 16. turner, web

41、er, the chinese legal system, and marshs critique, p. 6. 17. turner, weber, the chinese legal system, and marshs critique, p. 4. 18. turner, weber, the chinese legal system, and marshs critique, p. 5. 19. turner, weber, the chinese legal system, and marshs critique, pp. 4-5.34 max weber studies max

42、weber studies 2010.as rational as those of the civil law, and not even as rational as the empirical and inductive approach adopted by anglo-american law. apart from the lack of formal rationality, the substantive irratio-nality of traditional chinese law is also a widely accepted belief in the west.

43、 but this is open to dispute. max weber believed that the traditional chinese legal system was substantively irrational. two of the major reasons he gave for this are as the following: first, chinese magistrates and other law-enforcement officials made judicial decisions from case to case, in an unp

44、redictable and arbitrary way, without significant reference to written law codes. this is exactly what weber described as khadi justice,20 the ideal-type of substantively irrational law, where decisions are made on an ad hoc basis, or as weber put it, through informal judgments ren-dered in terms of

45、 concrete ethical or other practical valuations.21 secondly, weber regarded china as representing the purest type of patrimonial bureaucracy;22 that is, having ideal-type elements of both patrimonial and bureaucratic regimes. and the patrimonial offices were staffed not by technically qualified lega

46、l experts, but by humanistically educated generalists. the patrimonial ruler and his administrative law-enforcement officials are alike, characterized by the fact that their personal arbitrariness is limited only by sacred tradition.23 therefore, traditional chinese law lacked one of the nec-essary

47、conditions of western legal order: the separate status group of lawyersthe specially trained legal expert, which is an essential condition for the growth of legal realism. for these reasons, and some others as well, chinese law, according to weber, was closest to his ideal-type of substantively irra

48、tional law. robert marsh does not seem to agree with weber. he argues that, due to the lack of knowledge in the west about china, weber might be wrong in classifying traditional chinese law into the substantive irrationality of khadi style justice. marshs arguments are based on the new research into

49、 the qing code.24 20. the khadi is a judge in the moslem sharia court whose legal judgments, according to weber, take the form of pure arbitrariness. 21. max weber, economy and society: an outline of interpretive sociology (ed. guenther roth and claus wittich; berkeley, ca: university of california

50、press, 1978), p. 976. 22. max weber, economy and society, p. 1063. 23. marsh, webers misunderstanding of traditional chinese law, p. 283. 24. philip huang, code, custom and legal practice in china (stanford: stanford university press, 2001), p. 229. qian traditional chinese law v. weberian legal rat

51、ionality 35 max weber studies 2010.chinese officials arbitrary discretion in judicial decision making was much more limited than weber claimed, and what limited it was not primarily sacred tradition, but instead officials obligation to adjudi-cate according to the written law code. there was more le

52、gal expertise in the system than weber realized, and litigants were not merely passive victims of a despotic legal system.25 therefore, although marsh agrees that ching (qing) dynasty legal decisions were not “formally rational”, since they were not based upon purely formal, abstract legal reasoning

53、, he does say that:neither was chinese law primarily of the substantively irrational type, since legal decisions were not ad hoc, arbitrary rulings unpredict-ably delivered from case to case. the general principles upon which chinese legal decisions were based were drawn from confucian and legalist

54、philosophies, which though extrinsic to purely legal reason-ing precisely fit webers definition of substantively rational law.26 based on this new knowledge, marsh claims that traditional chi-nese law was in fact substantively rational instead of irrational and webers mistake was due to his lack of

55、knowledge about traditional chinese law. stephen turner, however, claims that none of marshs arguments matter to weber. because of the inherent insufficiency in the rationality of traditional chinese law, deductive law finding is impossible as chinese law was never organized in that way. common law

56、style of empirical induction is also impossible because of the lack of binding precedents. so this only leaves khadi justice, with ethics or other concrete factors causing the ad hoc legal decisions.27 the traditional chinese law is well known for the impacts made by ethics.28 this seems to support

57、turners argument. actually chi-nese people themselves strongly emphasize the ethical attributes of their legal tradition. in the studies of chinese legal history merging li (ethic) into law (yin li ru lv) is usually taken as one of the most essential feature of the traditional chinese law in contrast to the western legal traditions. one typical example of the impacts of con

溫馨提示

  • 1. 本站所有資源如無特殊說明,都需要本地電腦安裝OFFICE2007和PDF閱讀器。圖紙軟件為CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.壓縮文件請下載最新的WinRAR軟件解壓。
  • 2. 本站的文檔不包含任何第三方提供的附件圖紙等,如果需要附件,請聯(lián)系上傳者。文件的所有權益歸上傳用戶所有。
  • 3. 本站RAR壓縮包中若帶圖紙,網(wǎng)頁內(nèi)容里面會有圖紙預覽,若沒有圖紙預覽就沒有圖紙。
  • 4. 未經(jīng)權益所有人同意不得將文件中的內(nèi)容挪作商業(yè)或盈利用途。
  • 5. 人人文庫網(wǎng)僅提供信息存儲空間,僅對用戶上傳內(nèi)容的表現(xiàn)方式做保護處理,對用戶上傳分享的文檔內(nèi)容本身不做任何修改或編輯,并不能對任何下載內(nèi)容負責。
  • 6. 下載文件中如有侵權或不適當內(nèi)容,請與我們聯(lián)系,我們立即糾正。
  • 7. 本站不保證下載資源的準確性、安全性和完整性, 同時也不承擔用戶因使用這些下載資源對自己和他人造成任何形式的傷害或損失。

評論

0/150

提交評論